Harvard University,  FAS

Philosophy 257

Behavior and Other Minds

Asst. Prof James Pryor
Dept. of Philosophy


Criteria

Malcolm bases his criticism of the argument from analogy on the claim that it's a necessary condition of understanding "George is in pain" that you have a criterion for determining whether George is in pain.

What is a criterion? From the way Malcolm uses this term, we can distinguish the following features:

  1. A criterion for p is something that gives you reason to believe that p.

  2. It's part of understanding what it is for p to obtain that you recognize of p's criteria that they give you reason to believe that p.
    Some corollaries of this are:

  3. Knowing that a criterion for p is satisfied enables you to establish with certainty that p is true. (It's not clear how Malcolm is understanding "certainty." See Notes.)

  4. There is a "logical gap" between the presence of p's criteria and p's being true. There are conceivable situations in which the criteria are present but p is false. (Hence Malcolm can't be understanding "certainty" to mean that you have conclusive evidence for p: that is, evidence which it's impossible to have when p is false.)
    This suggests:

An Important Contrast

Consider the following claim:
BE. Such-and-such behavior gives you reason to believe the agent is in pain.
The criteria theorist says that we can know BE to be true on a priori grounds. However, other philosophers say this as well, for different reasons. It's important to keep these different positions distinct:

Why Should We Believe in Criteria?

Let's consider a line of reasoning that is supposed to establish the need for criteria. The criteria theorist often claims that:
  1. If you know about others' pains by induction from their behavior, then you have to know what pain is "from your own case."
However, the criteria theorist will argue that the assumption that you know what pain is "from your own case" leads to insuperable difficulties. Hence, he'll urge, we have to reject the view that we know about others' mental states by induction from behavior. And then appeal to criteria looks like the best remaining alternative to skepticism. (Here, the criteria theorist has to bring in some independent argument to show that a "perceptual" epistemology of other minds can't work.)

In fact, it's not so much the assumption that you acquire the concept of pain "from your own case" that the criteria theorist takes issue with. Rather, it's the following, more general claim:

  1. It's possible for you to know what pain is without yet knowing what would justify the ascription of pain to others.
The criteria theorist will argue that this assumption leads to insuperable difficulties; hence we should reject any epistemology which permits 2 to be true.

Well, what's supposed to be wrong with 2? One line of argument against 2 goes as follows. Suppose you accepted the following:

  1. It's impossible to speak a private language; so your mastery of any concept has to be subject to external checks.
This claim might be taken to entail:
  1. If you know what pain is, then it has to be possible for someone else to know that you know what pain is.
Claim 4 is controversial, but let's allow it for the sake of argument.

Many proponents of criteria believe that 2 and 4 are incompatible. They believe that no epistemology which permits 2 to be true can also respect 4. Rather, they argue:

  1. If 4, then knowing what pain is has to involve a recognition that certain sorts of behavior count as good reason to believe that the agent is in pain.
(Note that 5 doesn't merely say that knowing what pain is requires knowing what sorts of behavior would make an ascription of pain pragmatically appropriate. It says that knowing what pain is requires knowing what sorts of behavior would provide one with a good epistemic reason to ascribe pain to others.)

Accepting the consequent of 5 is tantamount to accepting the existence of criteria for pain. (I'm ignoring the requirement that criteria confer "certainty.")

I granted 4 for the sake of argument. So the important question is: why should we believe 5?

We haven't yet seen any argument to show that 2 and 4 are incompatible. If it were possible to know that someone else were in pain by an argument from analogy, or by inference to the best explanation of their observed behavior, then perhaps it would be possible to understand what it is for someone to be in pain, without yet having recognized what sorts of behavior warrant the ascription of pain to others. So if the argument from analogy or inference to the best explanation were viable epistemologies of other minds, then 2 and 4 would seem not to be incompatible. If that were so, then we ought not to accept 5.

So if the criteria theorist want us to accept 5, he has to supply independent arguments that the argument from analogy and other epistemologies of other minds which permit 2 to be true won't work. So we haven't yet seen a convincing argument from the impossibility of private languages against the argument from analogy and similar epistemologies. Even if we accept the impossibility of private languages, the burden of proof remains on the criteria theorist. (Malcolm seems to overlook this.)

Doubts about Criteria

Malcolm and the other criteria theorists claim that it's part of understanding the concept of pain that you recognize that certain sorts of behavior count as good evidence for pain. Well, if we wanted to, we could just stipulate that "pain" had such a meaning. But then we'd have no grounds for confidence that there were any actual or possible instances of pain, so understood.

To see this, consider concepts like "lunacy" and "puncture," that assume certain causal connections (lunacy is madness with a lunar cause; a puncture is the insertion of a sharp object which causes deflation). The usefulness and perhaps even the existence of such concepts depends on our belief that there is a causal correlation of the sort the concept assumes; but the existence of the concept does not guarantee that the correlation is genuinely there, nor that, if it's there, it will continue.

Why shouldn't the same go for concepts that assume certain evidential connections between behavior and the mental life of others (as Malcolm says "pain" does)? If the evidential connections are already in place, then we're entitled to use concepts like Malcolm's "pain," which apply only when the evidential connections hold; but we can't establish that the evidential connections are there just by using concepts which assume they're there. We need an argument that concepts which make such assumptions do genuinely apply to things.


[Phil 257] [James Pryor] [Philosophy Dept.]

Created by: James Pryor
Last Modified: Mon, Jul 17, 2000 6:58 PM